65 pages • 2 hours read
James SireA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Christian theism held sway for a long time in the West, but intellectual unity was broken at the dawn of the early modern period. This break was caused in part by numerous philosophical and theological quarrels (“family squabbles” and even “religious wars”) among Christians. Many began to feel both that the quarrels were pointless and that the supernatural claims of Christian theism were no longer tenable. Indeed, reason (as opposed to revelation) began to be viewed as the real and sole source of knowledge.
The idea, central to the theistic worldview, that the world as created by God was “rational, orderly, knowable” and that human beings had the capacity to study and know the world around them led to the development of modern science (37). (This view eventually won out over a Platonic Christian view according to which matter was something inferior to be transcended.) In particular, scientific thinkers began to conceive of the world as a “huge, well-ordered mechanism, a giant clockwork” (37). Deism was born as a philosophy that posited the existence of God, but without the specific claims of revealed religion. Historically, claims Sire, deism was the “result of the decay of robust Christian theism” (41).
Sire notes that the label “deism” actually covers a range of different but related beliefs held by various intellectual figures in the 17th and 18th centuries and after. Indeed, there was no single “orthodox” form of deism, and deists reached different conclusions on various issues. One distinction that can be made is between warm deists and cold deists. Warm deists held beliefs that were closer to traditional Christian theism, while cold deists pushed their beliefs farther away from Christian theism. Sire argues that defining deism in its more extreme (cold) form will help us understand its implications for the history of thought in a clearer way.
Deists believed in a transcendent God as an all-powerful being, force, or energy that created the universe, then “left it to run on its own” (39). This God is impersonal, not a being who loves and can be loved and worshiped in return. The laws of nature that God set in motion are absolute and determined by “a uniformity of cause and effect” (40). Thus, the universe is “closed,” which rules out any possibility for miracles or supernatural occurrences in which God “reorders” things.
Human beings, while personal in nature, are part of the clock-like system of the universe; one deist went so far as to describe man as a “machine,” though this was an extreme view. Deists differed on whether human beings had an existence beyond death, with some believing in an afterlife with rewards and punishments and some not.
The world is in its normal state and exactly as God created it; it is not “fallen or abnormal” (41). Because “whatever is, is right” (44), the universe reveals to us what is right and true. Human beings can, through their reason and senses alone, learn about the world around them and the principles of right and wrong and infer something of what God is like. Revelation is not necessary, and the scriptures are not divinely inspired but are human legends and creations. Deists chose various life goals as their core commitment, with a special stress on freedom, ethics, and public welfare.
Although deism had its heyday during the Age of Enlightenment (17th-18th centuries), it left its mark on society and culture, and various forms of deism continue to exist. According to Sire, modern deism includes such forms as: sophisticated scientific deism (Albert Einstein, Stephen Hawking), sophisticated philosophic deism (Anthony Flew, Vaclav Havel), and popular deism (sometimes manifested in the form of “soft Christianity” known as moralistic therapeutic deism).
Sire argues that popular deism—including the belief in either God as an abstract “force” or God as an approving, undemanding father figure—is the “vague belief” millions of people in the Western world, including both academics and ordinary people, unconsciously hold.
However, the original Enlightenment deism turned out to be an unstable worldview and eventually went into decline. Sire identifies five reasons for this:
Instead of surviving in its original form, Sire claims, deism morphed into naturalism, the subject of the next chapter.
Sire attempts to account for why theism was criticized and fell into disfavor, despite Sire’s contention regarding Christian Theism as the Most Coherent and Viable Worldview. He concedes that the question does not admit of an easy answer, but that “many forces operated to shatter” the West’s intellectual unity (35). Sire points to frustration with religious wars and strife as an important factor, and also the shift of intellectual authority from revelation to reason. The upshot was that the supernatural elements of Christianity came to be seen as implausible, and they began to fall away, leading to deism. For Sire, this is a common pattern in The Decline of Western Intellectual History: Each worldview that emerges over time constitutes a novel attempt to rework the answers to the eight basic questions, usually in an effort to salvage elements of Christian Theism that are considered valuable. In the end, however, the worldviews produced fail across the board to achieve the level of coherence and comprehensiveness that Christian Theism offers.
From here on in the book, while Sire will sometimes devote a section toward the end of the chapter to a critique of the worldview in question, he will also mix criticism in with his account of the worldview throughout the chapter. In Chapter 4, Sire’s account of deism is intermixed with critique because, for Sire, deism is riddled with inconsistencies. These inconsistencies are rooted in the fact that deism is (in Sire’s interpretation) a reduced version of Christian theism, achieved by subtracting various elements to arrive at a supposed “core” of truth. But for Sire, such a belief system is simply too thin to stand on its own, and a worldview that is defined by what it denies cannot last in the long run. Deism’s weakness was that it was parasitic on memories of Christianity, not a “robust” worldview in its own right.
Yet the fate of deism demonstrates a pattern among all the worldviews in the book: Instead of disappearing entirely, they morph seamlessly into another worldview, all the while coexisting with elements of other worldviews. Thus, elements of deism survived in culture up to the present day, as seen in “moralistic therapeutic deism.” Sire believes that this capacity of worldviews to survive and adapt is what makes understanding all of them relevant—to understand both where we are today and how we got there.
In the larger trajectory of the book, deism is significant as the worldview that started the long slide away from Christian theism that, for Sire, ended in despair and intellectual chaos. In Sire’s analysis, each chapter represents a further step away from the starting point, bringing out the logical consequences of the previous worldview.
Particularly in this chapter, Sire emphasizes the disagreements and divergences of opinion among thinkers in a single worldview; this is particularly true of deism, which housed a wide variety of opinion. However, in quoting Alexander Pope’s Essay on Man as an expression of deism, Sire fails to put forth the possibility that Pope was satirizing deist positions (as most literary scholars believe) rather than advocating them. This exemplifies the broader critique wielded against Sire’s work that his analyses of other worldviews are reductive and overly simplistic and, by painting with a broad brush, Sire mises nuances that might render a worldview more compelling or coherent.