logo

44 pages 1 hour read

Plato

The Republic

Nonfiction | Book | Adult

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapters 9-10Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Chapter 9 Summary: “The Supremacy of Good”

It is essential that, along with other attributes, the guardians who are rulers have knowledge of “the character of goodness” (230). This is the fundamental value underpinning all other values, morality, and understanding. Only then will the community be perfect. Socrates assesses, and dismisses, two common views of goodness, before giving his own. The first is that goodness is pleasure. The second is that goodness is knowledge. He argues that goodness cannot be pleasure since there are bad pleasures. Knowledge cannot be goodness either. This is because it leads to the circular position of saying that “knowledge of goodness” is goodness, hence leaving unanswered the meaning of goodness raised in the first place.

 

Instead, Socrates’ own view, relies upon three interrelated analogies. The first is that of the sun. Like the sun in relation to the visible world, it is the fundamental condition for all apprehension of truth and knowledge. The second analogy is that of “a line cut into two unequal sections” (237). Each half of the line is then subdivided again, and the resulting four parts represent the states of mind that are progressively closer to the good. The first part represents likenesses to material, or sensible objects, and is called “conjecture.” The second part is direct awareness of objects in the material world, “confidence.” The third represents “thought,” the engagement with the intelligible world beyond appearances. Finally, part four, represents “knowledge,” awareness of the grounds and conditions of intelligible knowledge.

Socrates complements these first two analogies with what he calls “an analogy for the human condition” (240). He asks Glaucon to imagine human beings chained in a cave. The cave opens onto the light, but the inhabitants are tied up facing away from the entrance and toward the dark cave wall. Closer to the entrance, there is a fire burning and casting light behind them. There is also a small wall, behind which various people can hide, and hold up objects in front of the fire, so that the shadows of these objects are visible on the cave wall. Thus, the shadows are all those chained in the cave know of the world. Socrates then describes what would happen if someone broke free from the cave and went out into the daylight. He explores how they would take time acclimating to sunlight and what would happen when they returned. He suggests that the cave inhabitants who are still tied up would treat such a person with incomprehension and disdain. They would not believe what he told them. This story is an allegory for the distinction between the visible realm and the higher, intelligible realm. It is also an allegory about the relationship between the philosopher and ordinary people.

Chapter 10 Summary: “Educating Philosopher Kings”

Chapter ten discusses the education of the philosopher kings. Mathematics and arithmetic will be important subjects for them. This is because they are useful for warfare, which philosopher kings will have to organise. More significantly, maths will be taught “in order to facilitate the mind’s turning away from becoming and towards truth and reality” (256). In other words, it is taught so that the philosopher is trained to enquire into the intelligible world of ideal concepts. This is in contrast to the sensible world of material objects. Mathematics, Socrates argues, encourages the mind to move away from such objects to the consideration of abstract principles. A similar point is made regarding the teaching of geometry. Astronomy and the study of music should also be taught, again with a focus on abstract ideas.

The most important subject, however, is dialectics. This is the skill of using rational argumentation to attain knowledge. It is the method of argument and counterargument that is employed by Socrates throughout The Republic. The ages at which the different subjects should be taught is discussed. Socrates suggests that dialectic should be learnt later. This is so that the young do not become overly rebellious by learning how to argue too soon. With the educational system for the philosopher kings now outlined, Socrates says that his account of the ideal community is now complete.

Chapters 9-10 Analysis

Having finished his account of the ideal community by the end of chapter seven, Socrates now adds a further important qualification. To make it “perfect” (332), the rulers of the society must also have knowledge of goodness. Indeed, he says that “there’s absolutely no point in having expert knowledge of everything else” (230) without this. But what is “goodness”? And how does one attain knowledge of it? To answer this Socrates uses three analogies, culminating in the analogy of the cave. In this last, famous, analogy Socrates describes the life of people unknowingly condemned to live their lives observing shadows on a cave wall. Meanwhile, one of them is forced up into the world of daylight beyond the cave. When he returns underground, he realizes he was living in a prison and what he thought was reality was only an illusion.

On one level, this is a relatively transparent allegory for Socrates’ hierarchy of understanding. This is the taxonomy outlined in the previous analogy of the line. As Socrates says, “The region which is accessible to sight should be equated with the prison cell, and the firelight there with the light of the sun” (243). As such, the shadows on the wall correspond to the lowest mode of understanding. This is brute perception, for example of trees and buildings. Next, corresponding to the firelight, is an understanding of the nature of perception itself. Socrates likens this to the sun in relation to everyday perception. More precisely, it is about understanding why and how we perceive objects in certain ways. For example, we understand how different types of light, or problems with one’s eyes, may affect our perception of a forest or lake. Alternatively, and more interestingly, we gain an understanding of how our emotions or desires can affect perception. For instance, the resemblance of someone in a crowd to a friend may cause my attention to focus on them and cause my other surroundings to become an amorphous backdrop.

Next, there is the journey upwards. This is the transition of the mind toward the intelligible realm. The phenomena in the outside world that are seen correspond to Socrates’ third category of understanding, “thought” (240). These are forms in the intelligible world “which only thought can see” (239). An example of this would be a mathematical proof, or an abstract concept like time. In neither case is there a perceivable object. Finally, there is the sun which brightens the outside world above the cave. This corresponds to Socrates’ fourth category of understanding, “knowledge.” This is understanding of the fundamental laws underpinning, and making possible, thought itself. It is also the highest possible value and source of all other values. It can be best understood as that which requires no further assumptions. It is the deepest possible point for thought to go, and one which, once attained, then illuminates the other three categories of understanding with new awareness. By its nature this cannot be explained through straightforward examples, which is why Socrates’ explanation is allegorical.

There is, however, another dimension to the allegory. This centres on the idea of philosophy as a calling or way of life. It also complements and enriches the metaphysical interpretation outlined. In this reading, the people of the cave are ordinary people. They have no awareness that there is anything beyond their everyday understanding, nor that anything could be better. Further, they are enslaved. While they believe they are free, their thoughts and feelings are manipulated. Indeed, they are manipulated precisely to believe that theirs is the best life, and to never question or escape it. This is why in the allegory they are tied up, unable to more even their heads. The man who is set free is someone awoken to philosophy. Significantly, this is done by someone else; we do not come to philosophy purely of our own volition. Plato perhaps has in mind for this role a significant teacher, as Socrates was for him. Or this role could be filled by a life-changing text, as Plato hopes The Republic will be for the reader.

The “pain and distress” (242) suffered by the man as he is “dragged forcibly away from there up the rough, steep slope” (242) is the suffering of the philosophical initiate. Not only is philosophy difficult, especially at first, but part of one will cling to the old, unthinking way of life. Finally, he gets to the daylight beyond the cave. This can be understood as the philosophical way of life proper and a life lived in genuine questioning and contemplation of the world. Once reached, it promises true freedom and self-realisation, as well as beauty in seeing the world now properly. Finally, the man returns to the cave. This is one of the most puzzling aspects of the allegory. Nevertheless, it can be understood as the attempt to communicate the value of philosophy to others. In thus trying to set others free, as he had been, he will risk humiliation and even death. Yet part of seeing the sun, and hence understanding the good, is awareness that he has at least an obligation to try. In this way, Plato suggests that the good cannot be attained merely in passive intellectual contemplation. Rather it is only fully realised through action and in becoming part of the good oneself.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text