39 pages • 1 hour read
PlatoA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
Socrates vows that he will speak the truth and what is just. He asks the court not to judge him for the content of his speech and not its delivery. He points out that he must defend himself against two accusers: those who brought the charges against him and “more long-standing accusers” who have, for years, accused him of being a wise man who “dabbles in theories” and “makes the weaker argument the stronger,” charges of which the jurors are inevitably aware (62). Though Socrates cannot bring them before the court, he will still take them into account in his defense.
Insisting that he has been misrepresented, Socrates states that he will explain how he got his “false reputation” as a self-proclaimed wise man (65). Socrates’s friend Chaerephon had visited Delphi to ask whether anyone was wiser than Socrates, and the Pythia, the priestess of Apollo, replied that no one was. Not believing her, Socrates went about conversing with “political experts,” concluding that they only thought themselves wise, and incurred their hatred when he tried to show them their error.
Socrates admits that he is wiser than they are by virtue of knowing that there are things that he does not know. Others, on the other hand, pretend to know things that they do not. Though he understood his actions were making everyone hate him, he also knew that his priority must be his “divinely instigated search” for the wisest man (67).
He moved on to poets, convinced that they would reveal themselves wiser than he, but came to the same conclusion. Their success was not because of their own wisdom but “natural talent” or divine inspiration, which they failed to realize and thought themselves wise (67).
The craftsmen were his next subject, and they exhibited the same mistake: believing that because they were skilled in their craft, they possessed wisdom in other matters as well.
His inquiries led Socrates to become hated because those he questioned assumed that he thought himself wiser than they. Socrates clarifies that the god is the wise one; his oracle meant to point out the limits of human wisdom. The wisdom Socrates possesses, then, is that he knows that he is not wise, whereas others do not. Socrates characterizes his conversations with men who believe themselves to be wise as an act of service to the god, which has left him impoverished, since he does not charge anyone for his conversations.
Socrates notes that wealthy young men took to following him around because they enjoyed seeing others tested. They practiced his technique among themselves and used it to test others who believed themselves to be wise about things they didn’t know about, and their targets became angry not only with the young men but also with Socrates. Because they did not want to admit having pretended to know things, they brought charges against. His accusers are speaking on behalf of the poets, political experts, craftsmen, and orators who Socrates has exposed.
Socrates turns to cross-examining Meletus, one of the men who brought the charges against him, asking him who can make the youth of Athens better men. His answer is everyone except Socrates. Socrates argues that training someone requires specialized knowledge, using horse training as an example. Thus, it cannot be true that just anyone could make the youth of Athens better.
His questioning further shows that it would be self-defeating to corrupt the youth intentionally because depraved people would be dangerous to have around. They would be more likely to do Socrates damage. Thus, Socrates concludes that Meletus’ charges are false. If Socrates has indeed been corrupting the youth, it was unintentional, meaning there are no grounds for court action.
Socrates questions Meletus about the charges concerning the gods. Meletus accuses him of not believing in any. Socrates accuses him of not being credible, since everyone knows that the beliefs Meletus attributes to Socrates are Anaxagoras’s. Further, Socrates points out, Meletus contradicts himself by saying that Socrates believes in new gods and that he doesn’t believe in any gods. He points out that it is not possible to believe in divine things but not divinity. Since Socrates believes in divine things, he must believe in gods. He concludes that Meletus has brought the charges either as a joke or because he could not come up with a credible charge.
Addressing a potential criticism against his behavior and the hatred it has incited, Socrates reiterates that the only consideration guiding a man’s behavior should be “whether his actions are just or unjust” and those of a good or bad man (76). He uses the example of Achilles in the Iliad, who did not consider whether avenging his companion Patroclus would lead to his death. He points out that just as Achilles took orders from his commanders at war, Socrates took orders from the god when he was commanded to live a philosophical life, examining himself and others, regardless of whether it led to his death. In that case, he would have been guilty of being both an atheist and unwise, as he would have been claiming to know things that he does not know.
If the court acquits him on the condition that he no longer continue his practice, he will not stop even if threatened with death because he is obeying what the god commanded him to do, which is to make his fellow citizens better men. They cannot harm him because a lesser man cannot damage a better one. By defending himself, he is defending these men and the city itself, since they will not find another man like him who is willing to prod them to care more for virtue than anything else, even to the point of disregarding his own affairs.
If the assembly finds it strange that he only practices his method as a private citizen, Socrates tells them, this is because he would not have survived long as a public figure and thus would not have been able to benefit men and the city as he has.
He cites two examples of actions he took while serving the city in a public capacity that prove he has never acted out of fear of death but only love of what is just: the court case that resulted in putting to death the generals who lost at the battle of Arginusae in 406 and his refusal to carry out the orders of the Thirty Tyrants to bring a man to Athens for execution.
He asserts that he is the same man in public and private. If he had corrupted youths, surely they or their fathers would have brought charges against him previously. Instead, they sit in the audience ready to defend him.
He asserts that he will not bring his family or young sons to the court or to beg to be acquitted. If he cannot convince the jurors that it is just to acquit him, then it would be wrong for him to be let off. He would be convincing them to break their own oaths. He asks them not to hold that against him, for if he were to use emotional appeals, then he would indeed be behaving impiously and proving himself an atheist, which he asserts that he is not.
After Socrates is found guilty, he gives a second speech in which he professes that his only surprise is that the margin for conviction was so small. Meletus has proposed the death penalty. Socrates addresses what should be done with him, given that he has sacrificed everything most people care about to serve the men of the city.
First, he suggests that his “penalty” should be to be fed at public expense (86). A fine or exile would not be acceptable, the former because Socrates could not pay it, the latter because if his own city does not want him, he has no reason to believe any other would. He would spend his last years as a fugitive.
His friends in the audience pass him a note offering to contribute money for a fine, but he is condemned to death a second time, by a larger margin.
In his final address to court, he asserts that he has been condemned because he refuses to resort to “effrontery and shamelessness” by “wailing and lamenting” (89). He reaffirms that he would not change anything about his defense because he behaved according to what he believes is just. Fear of death does not influence his actions. He predicts that those who have put him to death will be worse off without him because they cannot murder their way out of being reproached for wrong-thinking actions.
He concludes that what has happened to him must be a good thing. If death is like sleep, then eternity and a good night’s sleep will be indistinguishable. If death is moving to an underworld where the great judges and heroes reside, then he will die happily since he will have a chance to continue practicing his examination of men and women.
He concludes that the best way to get back at him and act justly would be to correct his own sons, if they do wrong in the future, as he has corrected the men of Athens.
The careful construction of Socrates’s speech belies his claim that he is not a good speaker, a claim that seems designed to set him apart from the typical way things are done. Well-designed and attractively delivered speeches may have been part of what created problems for Athens by swaying the public towards bad decisions, especially during the turbulent fifth century BCE that was plagued by direct and proxy wars against rival regional power Sparta. Athens’ simultaneous attempt to expand its empire by launching an expedition to Sicily eventually ended disastrously; Athens lost not only the war against Sparta but also its empire and even, temporarily, its democracy in 403 BCE.
Socrates’s statement is a declaration that he will seek what is just, always and above all other concerns, and a plea to the jury to do likewise, focusing not on whether his speech pleases them but whether it is just. After he is condemned to death, he reiterates his request, saying that he refuses to employ emotional rhetorical appeals, and is condemned again, by a larger margin. The purpose of his single-minded focus on reasoning becomes especially clear in Phaedo when Socrates addresses the importance of preparing the soul for death by distancing it from the body even during life. To use artful, emotional techniques to sway the jury would not be just, according to Socrates, because it would encourage reliance on the physical body and its flawed perceptions rather than on the soul.
Socrates’s acknowledgment of both the men who brought charges against him and the men of the jury who are likely biased against him reveals the important role public opinion would have played in the Athenian court. There was no one other than the jury to determine whether laws were being applied faithfully and no one to appeal to if things did not go the defendant’s way. The 500-person jury was intended to prevent bribery but had the unintended consequence of giving public opinion an outsized influence. Socrates had been lampooned in Athenian comedies for decades by the time of the trial, and while scholars debate whether these sendups would have impacted jurors’ decisions, the larger point about public perception still holds. Socrates had a reputation for being annoying and a gadfly. Even when the stakes are life or death, he persists in revealing human limitations though he knows this frustrates those who will decide his fate.
Socrates begins his defense by pointing out that he has been misrepresented as someone who thinks he is wise and who pushes his views on the youth of Athens. The story of the oracle at Delphi portrays him as one who observes the traditional religious rituals. Oracles are not straightforward; they require interpretation. (Herodotus’s Histories offers the story of Croesus as a cautionary tale on the hazards of over-enthusiastically interpreting oracles.) Socrates’s conversations are how he attempts to understand what the god Apollo, god of prophecy and music among other things, is trying to communicate through the oracle. Socrates clarifies that he is not promoting specific knowledge but a way of approaching knowledge. The starting point is to admit what one does not know, the very thing he accuses his fellow citizens of being unwilling or unable to do, as exemplified in the Euthyphro.
At the end of this portion of his defense, Socrates interprets the oracle to mean that humans cannot know everything; there are limits to human knowledge. This maneuver gives credit to the wisdom of the oracle rather than to himself while simultaneously validating his process. It also demonstrates how Socrates could have become so widely disliked and why this is wrong. His process was a service to the god as it brought his wisdom, via the oracle, to the widest possible audience. Socrates’s method began in order to test the meaning of the oracle. The process of interpreting the oracle became his project; he used questioning and his unique expertise to educate the men of Athens about their limits. He does not claim to know what wisdom or justice are, only to have a process that can reveal what they are not.
That process is incorporated into his defense as Socrates cross-examines Meletus. Through questions, Socrates reveals Meletus’ accusations to be poorly considered. Meletus contradicts himself repeatedly and provides no evidence for his claims. While revealing the limitations and hollowness of Meletus’s accusations, Socrates simultaneously demonstrates what has made him an unpopular figure. The ease with which he can expose others’ intellectual limitations and character flaws has made him widely disliked. Though Socrates highlights, in his defense, the ways that he honors the gods and citizens of Athens, his methods are unorthodox and nonconformist, rendering him a threat to the city in the eyes of its public.
By Plato