logo

74 pages 2 hours read

Alexander Hamilton, James Madison, John Jay

The Federalist Papers

Nonfiction | Essay Collection | Adult | Published in 1787

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Federalist No. 23-Federalist No. 36Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Federalist No. 23 Summary: “The Necessity of a Government as Energetic as the One Proposed to the Preservation of the Union”

Hamilton states that the powers of national defense—raising armies, building fleets, and directing the operations of both—should exist “without limitation” because “[t]he circumstances that endanger the safety of nations are infinite, and for this reason no constitutional shackles can wisely be imposed on the power to which the care of it is committed” (111).

Although the framers of the Articles of Confederation realized this, they failed to grant the federal government the necessary authority to carry out these duties effectively. Whereas the federal government of the Confederation requisitions soldiers and men through state quotas (an arrangement shown to be a failure in Federalist No. 22) the government of the proposed Constitution would be empowered to levy troops and marshal supplies directly, enforcing its laws on individuals rather than on the states.

Federalist No. 24 Summary: “The Powers Necessary to the Common Defense Further Considered”

Hamilton discusses provisions found in state constitutions of Pennsylvania and North Carolina recommending that standing armies should not be maintained during times of peace because they are “dangerous to liberty.” He goes on to explain why a similar provision is not found in the US Constitution under consideration for ratification. For one, Britain and Spain each hold territory adjacent to the United States, and it is possible that the pair may become allies in the future. This, he adds, would only embolden the Indigenous peoples on the Western frontier, whose presence already requires garrisons in the Western states. Finally, Hamilton believes it is imperative that the United States build a navy, and to do so requires dockyards, arsenals, and fortifications that must be staffed by military garrisons.

Federalist No. 25 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (The Powers Necessary to the Common Defense Further Considered)”

Hamilton further expounds on the desirability of a standing army raised and maintained by the federal government. Absent this, states like New York—which is particularly vulnerable to foreign and Indigenous attacks—would be solely responsible for their own protection. In turn, Hamilton believes this could result in an arms race between the states which would only intensify the threat of violent factions and civil war. Finally, Hamilton revisits the example of Massachusetts, which recently raised troops to quell Shays’ Rebellion without first gaining permission from the Congress of the Confederation—further proof that states feel empowered to defy the Articles of Confederation as it suits them.

Federalist No. 26 Summary: “The Idea of Restraining the Legislative Authority in Regard to the Common Defense Considered”

Hamilton argues that the clause in the proposed Constitution requiring legislative approval every two years for the raising and expansion of armies during peacetime is just and wise. He says no further restrictions should be applied, adding that calls to do so are rooted in “a zeal for liberty more ardent than enlightened” (124).

Federalist No. 27 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (The Idea of Restraining the Legislative Authority in Regard to the Common Defense Considered)”

Hamilton returns to the objections that the only way citizens will comply with federal laws under the proposed Constitution is if a military force compels them. He argues that citizens will follow laws based on whether they are just and well-administered, not whether they stem from the federal government or the state government. For the reasons the authors have already laid out supporting a strong federal government, Hamilton believes it will be less likely under the Constitution that military force will be needed to achieve compliance with the law.

Federalist No. 28 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (The Idea of Restraining the Legislative Authority in Regard to the Common Defense Considered)”

Hamilton writes that insurrection and sedition are always a threat. In the case of small insurrections, state militias may be called upon to quell them. However, in the case of large revolts like Shays’ Rebellion, a federal army is needed. Returning to the advantages of a Union versus a loose confederation, Hamilton argues that a despotic federal regime will find it difficult to maintain control of the entire United States through military means. By contrast, a despotic state regime under the current Articles of Confederation will find it easier to maintain tyranny in its limited territory.

Federalist No. 29 Summary: “Concerning the Militia”

Hamilton quotes the proposed Constitution concerning militias, writing that the federal government will be empowered “to provide for organizing, arming, and disciplining the militia [...] RESERVING TO THE STATES RESPECTIVELY THE APPOINTMENT OF THE OFFICERS, AND THE AUTHORITY OF TRAINING THE MILITIA” (138). He is shocked that this clause has generated controversy, given that it is natural for the central government to pay such an active role in issues of national defense, for reasons detailed in earlier essays. Hamilton also dismisses fears that militias are a threat to liberty, writing, “Where in the name of commonsense, are our fears to end if we may not trust our sons, our brothers, our neighbors, our fellow-citizens?” (140).

Federalist No. 30 Summary: “Concerning the General Power of Taxation”

Hamilton condemns the current system of taxation, by which the federal government is forced to rely on quotas and requisitions from each of the 13 states. For reasons outlined in previous essays, these quotas are poorly calculated and difficult to enforce. And while some anti-Federalists are willing to allow the federal government to collect “external taxes” such as import taxes, this will not be sufficient to ensure the nation’s survival—especially if a war breaks out. Instead, the federal government should be allowed to collect “internal taxes” directly from the citizens.

Federalist No. 31 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (Concerning the General Power of Taxation)”

Hamilton bemoans the fact that individuals easily accept complex mathematical principles as correct but are unable to do the same with principles of morality and politics, namely the principle that the federal government’s powers should include general taxation of its people. Some object that the federal government, if given unlimited powers of taxation, would encroach on the states’ own powers of taxation and deprive them of revenue. However, Hamilton points out that the opposite is more likely since in a republic power is ultimately held by the people, and state governments have more direct influence over the people than the federal government.

Federalist No. 32 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (Concerning the General Power of Taxation)”

Looking to specific clauses in the Constitution, Hamilton lays to rest fears that the states would be prohibited from collecting their own taxes. As he points out, all existing state powers are preserved except those that the Constitution gives the federal government exclusive power to carry out. For example, on the matter of taxes, only the federal government can collect import and excise taxes, but that does not prevent the states from collecting other forms of tax revenue.

Federalist No. 33 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (Concerning the General Power of Taxation)”

Hamilton points to two clauses in the Constitution which critics claim pose existential threats to local governments and personal liberty. The first states that the federal legislature can “make all laws which shall be NECESSARY and PROPER for carrying into execution THE POWERS by that Constitution vested in the government of the United States” (155). The second refers to the laws and treaties passed by the federal government as “the SUPREME LAW of the land” (158).

In response to these critics, Hamilton says the meaning of the Constitution would be the same if these clauses were removed, just as it would be the same if the clauses were written on every page. He adds that the rest of the Constitution makes clear that overstepping of the federal government’s jurisdiction into the domain of the states—for example, by passing a law prohibiting the states from levying taxes—would be “a usurpation of power not granted by the Constitution” (158). In modern terminology, it would be unconstitutional.

Federalist No. 34 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (Concerning the General Power of Taxation)”

Hamilton discusses the concept of “CONCURRENT JURISDICTION”—meaning administrative duties carried out by both federal and state governments, like direct taxation. In the case of taxes, this is neither inconsistent nor redundant because states will limit their taxation efforts within “A VERY NARROW COMPASS” (160) of uses specific to each state. Meanwhile, the federal government, charged as it is with the safety and security of the entire nation, enjoys an unlimited right to raise whatever revenue is needed to meet that end.

Federalist No. 35 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (Concerning the General Power of Taxation)”

Hamilton returns to the question of what may happen if the federal government is barred from raising revenue except through duties on foreign imports. If this were the case, the federal government would inevitably raise import taxes to exorbitant rates, encouraging smuggling and leaving merchants to pass on the expenses to consumers. As a result, inequality would increase both within states and between them—particularly between manufacturing states and non-manufacturing states, the latter of which are more dependent on imports.

A second major objection to the Constitution is that the House of Representatives is too small for each member to sufficiently represent all the occupations held by their constituents. Hamilton counters that blue collar workers like mechanics and manufacturers need not be elected to Congress because these individuals will generally elect merchants, a class of citizens who share their interests. The “learned professions”—namely, lawyers—will be satisfied to elect other lawyers to represent their interests. Finally, landowners are generally fixated on a single policy interest: keeping land taxes low. Therefore, it matters little whom they elect to represent them, as long as the representatives support low land taxes.

Federalist No. 36 Summary: “The Same Subject Continued (Concerning the General Power of Taxation)”

On the question of how the federal government can appropriately tax so many distant municipalities, each with its own peculiarities, Hamilton’s answer is simple: ask the states’ representatives for help. Even more to the point, the federal government can and should take advantage of the existing tax apparatus in each state.

Hamilton also expresses his personal distaste for poll taxes, which exist in some states. However, he also admits that the federal government would be within its rights to administer poll taxes if its representatives voted to do so.

Federalist No. 23-Federalist No. 36 Analysis

The key question at the heart of these essays involves how to make the federal government empowered and energetic enough to protect the people without needlessly infringing on the rights of individuals. Building off the notion of the social contract discussed by Jay in Federalist No. 2, Hamilton and Madison grant that some liberties must be sacrificed to this end. The authors’ key overarching point here is that individuals already give up certain rights in their social contract with states. For the purpose of national defense and foreign policy, governance can only work when there is also a strong federal government. This is, in short, the heart of Federalism.

A keystone issue through which the authors examine this question involves "standing armies." Modern readers may be surprised at the amount of space all three authors devote to discussions of standing armies during peacetime. In 21st-century America, many take for granted the existence of a military that is well-trained and easily mobilized, even when the country is not at war. Moreover, even in 2007 at the height of antiwar sentiment pertaining to the Iraq War, 84 percent of Americans held a favorable view of the military (Rosentiel, Tom. “Iraq and Vietnam: A Crucial Difference in Opinion.” Pew Research Center. 22 Mar. 2007. https://www.pewresearch.org/2007/03/22/iraq-and-vietnam-a-crucial-difference-in-opinion/).

Yet from both a historical and social perspective, 18th-century Americans viewed the military differently. While Madison largely looks to historical precedent to outline the dangers of standing militaries, his patriot ally Samuel Adams in 1776 called contemporary armies “nurseries of vice” and “the grand engine of despotism” (Bakken, Tim. The Cost of Loyalty: Dishonesty, Hubris, and Failure in the US Military. London: Bloomsbury. 2020). Moreover, Americans still recalled the oppressive and costly presence of the British Army in the colonial days, during the French & Indian War and in the buildup to the American Revolution. So while many of the political conflicts discussed in The Federalist Papers remain highly relevant in the 21st century, the debate over standing armies is not one of them.

For Hamilton’s part, he is much better able to tolerate standing armies than Madison, making this one of the few issues where there is significant daylight between the men in The Federalist Papers. However, just because Hamilton and Madison seem united in their overarching philosophies and beliefs, the truth is much more complicated. This seemingly slight disagreement over standing armies foreshadows a broader rift that will grow between the two men in the 1790s, when Madison will break away from Hamilton’s Federalist Party to form the Republican-Democratic Party over opposition to the national bank.

On the subject of national finances, Hamilton goes into extensive detail in these essays concerning the federal government’s ability to raise revenue through taxation and tariffs. This is an area of significant interest and expertise for Hamilton, who would go on to serve as the United States’ first Secretary of the Treasury. In that role, he executed on many of the financial policies proposed and implied here, including the creation of a tariff system, normalized trade relations with Britain, and a taxation scheme allowing the federal government to fund the states’ debts.

One may wonder, however, how sincere Hamilton is in his contention that the states are more likely to encroach on the federal government’s capacity for taxation, rather than the reverse. An instructive example can be found in the Whiskey Rebellion of the 1790s, a revolt in Pennsylvania over Hamilton’s federal tax on whiskey, the first of its kind to be placed on a domestic product. Ultimately, President Washington commanded both federal troops and state militiamen to quell the rebellion. While the intervention was looked upon favorably because it did not result in any bloodshed, it served as a stark reminder of the federal government’s power to enforce unpopular tax policies.

Finally, these essays offer some insight into Hamilton’s beliefs concerning elites and egalitarianism. Throughout this life and for centuries after his death, Hamilton faced accusations that his policies and principles favored the aristocracy—a serious charge given Americans’ inborn distaste for the rigid social classes and titles of nobility found in Great Britain. One can sense this in Federalist No. 35, in which Hamilton dismisses the concern that wealthy merchants and lawyers will make up the vast majority of directly and indirectly elected officials. In a 2016 New York Times article, Cornell political theorists Jason Frank and Isaac Kramnick write of Hamilton’s “contemptuous attitude toward the lower classes,” adding that he was “perfectly comfortable with the antidemocratic implications of his economic vision” (Frank, Jason and Isaac Kramnick. “What ‘Hamilton’ Forgets About Alexander Hamilton.” The New York Times. 10 Jun. 2016. https://www.nytimes.com/2016/06/11/opinion/what-hamilton-forgets-about-alexander-hamilton.html).

Yet other scholars say that while Hamilton’s loyalties may have swung closer to the intellectual elites than yeoman farmers, it is inaccurate to call him “undemocratic,” at least in the modern sense of the word. In his book The Political Philosophies of Alexander Hamilton, historian Michael P. Federici paints a nuanced portrait of Hamilton as a man who preferred meritocratic aristocracies to hereditary nobility and who advocated on behalf of a mixed constitution containing republican principles, like the direct election of House representatives, along with countervailing elements such as an unelected federal judiciary without term limits. (Federici, Michael P. The Political Philosophy of Alexander Hamilton. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. 2012.)

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text