logo

42 pages 1 hour read

John Locke, C. B. Macpherson, ed.

Second Treatise of Government

Nonfiction | Essay / Speech | Adult | Published in 1689

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Themes

The Natural Rights of Man

The natural rights of man is perhaps one of the broadest, and most singularly important, themes of both the Second Treatise and the Enlightenment. While Locke didn’t invent concepts like the state of nature, the state of war, property rights, or the right to revolution, he did articulate them in such a way that his interpretation and presentation of those ideas have come to represent the central definitions for them. Locke’s work wouldn’t become popular for another century or so after publication—but when it did, it led to some of the greatest, and bloodiest, periods of social upheaval in Western history.

Again, Locke’s assertion that men exist in a natural state of peace without a monarch, sovereign, or general leader was not new, but his belief that this state is the base relationship between human beings, something that can’t ever really or fully be left, was a fundamentally unique perspective. Conversely, a political predecessor of his, Thomas Hobbes, viewed the state of nature as an ancient and temporary state that human beings abdicated when they opted to live in political society. While this assertion may not entirely be off the mark, it’s the open-ended potential of Locke’s interpretation that won him so much acclaim later in the life of his work. Likewise, Locke’s idea of the state of war—which is somewhat closer to Hobbes’s idea of the state of nature—as a temporary and brutal relationship between people who have encroached on each other’s natural rights, was a novel concept, given that it does not entirely strip people of their capacity for reason but instead argues that it is their reason alone—which is not destroyed in the state of war, but rather lays dormant—that will lift them out of such an antipathetic dialectic.

Property rights as Locke conceives of them would have been almost inconceivable to many people of his time. Though the Enlightenment was in full swing, many still labored under a kind of fiefdom, where they worked on land owned in common by the state—and therefore by the monarch. In this structure, the common people owned very little and saw very little in their life as their own, including their labor. By asserting that property is not simply an object but an extension of person by way of creation, Locke redefined what it means to own and to create. Many who are unfamiliar with his writings believe that property rights mean nothing more than pure ownership of an estate, of land, of objects—but Locke’s idea of property rights is more complex. He wanted to cement a philosophical and political definition for a person’s right to own whatever they may create with their own hands. Much in the same way that parents have a right in some capacity to their children, Locke believed everyone has a right to the product of their own labor, which he would call their property.

Following these two ideas is the most radical and dangerous proposition in the entire Treatise. The idea that a people have the right to choose their rulers and actively depose them when they see fit would have unsettled any monarch in Locke’s era. While the power of monarchy was waning across Europe, it would still be another 100 years before the most powerful monarchy of all—Britain—was deposed from its own colony, and it would be another 60 years after that before a wave of revolutions would sweep monarchy off the table of the European Continent altogether.

This assertion completely changes the relationship a people has with their ruler. Instead of making the people subject to a rule for as long as the ruler remains alive—which in the case of a monarch could be upward of 50 years, and in the case of a legislative body could be almost indefinite—Locke’s system makes the ruler subject to the people. This goes along with his belief that a political society was secondary to the community, the collection of people in any given area who agreed to a common bond and relationship between themselves. In proposing such a radical notion, Locke somewhat immortalized the idea of a people’s ability for self-government absent a necessarily “political” structure.

Community Versus Political Society

A crucial theme that runs throughout the Second Treatise is the difference between a community—meaning a collection of people, whether a town, a city, a country, or otherwise—and the political society they install to help govern themselves.

In Locke’s view, because human beings are in the state of nature almost perpetually, it makes sense that there is an unbreakable bond between all people at all times, and that is doubly true for groups who decide to band together and form communities. This bond and relationship between people forms the basis of all other systems of organization, and in a marked break from his contemporaries Locke believes that human beings, whether they know it or not, inhabit one large community absent of political structure. Other thinkers, like Hobbes, would have disagreed immensely and argued that in the state of nature, human beings are always viciously individual and cannot conceive of, much less form, a cooperative union with each other.

However, Locke does admit that political society is necessary for one express purpose: to act as a judge, an arbiter, in disputes between community members. Without an impartial system or person to appeal to, there is no way for disputes to truly and fairly be settled other than by extermination or some base and ultimately unfair agreement between the two parties.

To manage other issues, Locke divides the political system into three distinct parts—the federative (judicial), which is responsible for objectively mediating the disputes between members of the community; the legislative, a body created to safeguard the political system’s founding laws and to fashion new laws in respect to the wishes of the old while paying heed to the needs of the present and potential outcomes of the future; and the executive, an office responsible for carrying out the laws created by the legislative, designed so that neither of the two has an inordinate amount of power over each other or the people.

These three bodies—which have come to constitute the general makeup of most modern, or at least most Western, democracies—are given immense power and responsibility, with two caveats: They are not in any way superior to the people, despite their position, and they are to behave honorably and with rectitude toward their duty. If they fail in either of these two charges, the community is well within its rights to dispose of them and constitute a new political society, or at the very least amend the current one, as they see fit.

The People’s Relationship to Rulers

Many contemporary or establishment theorists of Locke’s age would have sided with Robert Filmer’s argument that because man is a demonstrably brutish creature, he needs a strong, almost authoritarian figure to guide him throughout his life and across the many aspects of society he may traverse. This postulated relationship wasn’t always a negative. Once again, Hobbes comes to the forefront: He believed in the idea of a strong sovereign, but many take his position to be strictly in favor of monarchy, much like how many may take Locke’s position to be strictly in favor of democracy. This was not the case with either, and Hobbes makes clear in Leviathan that the relationship between a people and their ruler is sacrosanct and deserves an intimacy and reverence that, if transgressed by the ruler, renders the agreement—the social contract—between the two invalid. In such a case, the population would return to a state of nature until a new sovereign either arose or was chosen.

Hobbes’s idea of politics was quite literally an idealistic one; his goal was to sketch the blueprint of an ideal political society, one in which a near-perfect sovereign, either a single person or a committee of sorts, could continually be renewed by the mechanisms of the society itself, freeing the common people from the fear of their leader betraying their trust.

Conversely, Locke’s conception is more realistic; he places much trust and has a lot of care for people in general, but he also understands that some in power see themselves not so much as shepherds but as salesmen, whose only responsibility is not to the welfare of the people but to the welfare of the state that ensures their high and comfortable status. To maintain this position, quite a few of them will engage in unjust and disingenuous behavior to convince the people that the system, despite any apparent flaws, is working as planned, and that it is not the ruler who must address these issues but the people.

In such a case, Locke’s idea of how a people relate to their ruler becomes indispensable. The notion that a political society and all its trappings—especially its attendants (i.e., politicians)—is subordinate to the community it serves is a landmark thought in the modern formation of political relationships. Distinguishing between a people and their ruler as two separate entities that work in tandem—and especially asserting that a people possess inherent and natural, quite literally God-given, abilities to shape their society, independent of any political system—was groundbreaking at the time and remains so today.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text