logo

44 pages 1 hour read

Aristotle

Nicomachean Ethics

Nonfiction | Book | Adult

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Books 7-10Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Book 7 Summary

Book 7 considers the other side of virtue. Aristotle explores three conditions that he suggests humans should actively attempt to evade: “vice, incontinence, and bestiality” (117). In this work, bestiality refers to being more like an animal than like a human. Aristotle suggests that this is a rare state but one that is more often attributed to non-Greek peoples. He offers cannibalism as an example of bestiality. This vice is divided into two parts: simple and diseased. A person with simple vice may have notions of bestiality but not act upon them, but a person with diseased vice cannot help but submit to the extreme and violent acts associated with bestiality. Aristotle suggests that bestiality is not as bad as vice, as it is not a result of conscious choice; however, it is more terrifying because the components of the soul needed for one to act virtuously are completely missing.

Aristotle devotes much of the book to the concept of incontinence, addressing various puzzles and previous modes of thought about the topic. The term “incontinence” refers to a lack of self-restraint, or hedonism. To better distinguish incontinence from vice, Aristotle engages in a series of puzzles exploring incontinence.

His predecessors did not subscribe to the concept of incontinence. They did not think a person would act in a way that was contrary to their knowledge; rather, incorrect actions were the result of ignorance. Aristotle rejects this idea, but he also does not attribute incontinence to belief or a lack of conviction. He attempts to prove this view of incontinence, which sharply contradicts Socrates’s views. Aristotle suggests that, just as is true with virtues, incontinence is completely a question of pleasure and pain. The two types of pleasure—choice-worthy and necessary—center on good pleasures that are worth pursuit (honor, wealth) and pleasures that are vital (sexual intercourse, food). Incontinence takes these pursuits to excess.

Although incontinence and intemperance are similar, Aristotle distinguishes them from one another. An intemperate person makes an active choice to pursue the extremes of pleasure, but the incontinent person is overtaken by the ferocity of appetite. In this way, intemperance is a worse vice than incontinence. The intemperate person thinks that the pursuit of something desired is always good. The incontinent person knows that it is not but pursues it anyway. The extremes on each side of this spectrum are temperance and continence. The continent person has a desire for pleasure, but the temperate person cannot desire anything that does not align with reason.

As Aristotle explores incontinence and its relationship with intemperance, he also refers to softness. Incontinence indicates being overcome by pleasure, but softness refers to being overcome by pain. The incontinent person will actively choose to pursue excess pleasure, and the soft person will avoid experiences out of fear of pain. Resistance is the opposing force to softness; the resistant person overcomes this fear of pain.

Aristotle completes Book 7 by studying pleasure. He notes pleasure’s significant role in both vice and virtue. The extreme pursuits of pleasures reveal themselves through vice. However, just as with pain, pleasures help inform individuals of right actions and what is good.

Book 8 Summary

Aristotle focuses in this book on friendship, a virtue that he states is “most necessary for our life” (141). He suggests that friendship is needed by all individuals, wealthy or poor. Friends help guide and protect one another from falling into the hands of vice. They encourage one another to be the best versions of themselves. Aristotle asserts that friendship makes up the fabric of existence and the success of humans as a species.

He presents several thoughts on friendship, including the notion that humans tend to become friends with those who are most like them and the theory that friends who are similar tend to fight more often. The pursuit of friendship is about both goodness and pleasure. Having friends is pleasurable, but it also contributes to good.

Three types of friendship align with three types of love. The first type of love sustains friendships with intentions of the good and delivers respect to both parties. The second, “love for the sake of utility,” consists of friendships that are rooted in the benefits each person gains from them (143). The third, “love for the sake of pleasure” (143), consists of friendships that are based simply on enjoying another person’s company so long as it continues to be entertaining. These last two types center on the self; they are both based on what one gains from the friendship and are not as lasting as the first. They tend to dissolve when one or both people fail to receive the goods—pleasure, status—that the friendship was predicated upon. These types of incomplete friendships are not restricted to those who are bad or trend toward vice. All people enter incomplete friendships. However, good people or those who actively seek virtue are more likely to obtain complete friendships; they are more desirable as friends and more lovable.

A friendship bound in love is about helping one another to achieve good, or happiness. This is a lasting friendship. Aristotle also suggests that these types of friendships do not come around often; they require time and effort to build and maintain. Most people have only a few complete friendships. Those with many so-called friends have an abundance of the other two types of friendships. A friendship rooted in love for the other person is also built upon equality. It is mutually beneficial for both people in it, and both parties in the friendship regard each other with love and admiration. Friendships that rely upon hierarchal structures are disproportionate and, therefore, not examples of pure and complete friendships.

Aristotle proposes that complete friendships are more focused on giving love than on receiving it. Both people in the relationship are focused more on expressing love outwardly than on getting something from the other person. In this way, they are equal. This rejects the idea that people are friends only with those who are like them; Aristotle suggests that this is true only if the similarity is that of equal of feeling and virtue.

Communities are built upon friendships and could not exist without them, and all communities contribute to larger political communities. Both friendship and justice play substantial roles in communities and political systems. For example, a king may have a friendship of utility with his subjects; the relationship is mutually beneficial for both parties. Each has something to gain from the other. When this relationship stops being advantageous, the friendship of utility dissolves. This friendship can also survive only so long as justice remains in play. If justice is removed, the superiority that a king has over his subjects renders the relationship incapable of friendship.

Another type of community is the family. Parents love their children as an extension of themselves, and children love their parents as they get older and gain a better understanding of the world. Children then see their parents as the source of their life and well-being and love them for it. Just as in these other structures, there are varying types of friendships. Equality and hierarchal structures play a role in the types of friendships that emerge from family structures.

Aristotle closes the book by examining disputes in equal and unequal friendships. Friendships based on utility are prone to disagreements. Since both parties expect to receive something advantageous from the partnership, the possibility of discord is great as those balances fluctuate. These types of friendship always end badly. Complete friendships based on virtue do not have these problems with disproportion; since social or financial advancement is not the purpose of the relationship, no one is hurt or leaves the friendship when it doesn’t result in material gain. Hierarchal structures also contribute to disputes in friendships. One party may believe it is more deserving than the other, tipping the balance heavily to one side.

Book 9 Summary

In this book, Aristotle continues his study of friendship and its contribution to good and happiness. He presents advice and analysis of friendships in which both parties seek different aims. For example, sometimes one person loves the other in pursuit of pleasure and desire, and the other loves for utility or monetary gain. Aristotle considers this imbalance as he also raises questions about the conflicts that arise within friendships. He acknowledges that friendships are riddled with exceptions. He exercises caution in attempting to create a code of ethics that can be applied universally to all people and all types of friendships. The imbalances in friendships are indicative of their complexity.

Often, friendships dissolve. It is not a surprise when this happens to incomplete friendships. Because they are built upon mutual advantages, they come apart at the seams when those advantages begin to be stripped away. Aristotle suggests that humans must be aware of the types of friendships they enter and never assume that they are experiencing complete friendships predicated upon love when the opposite is true. One of the puzzles Aristotle presents is what a person should do if their friend, who was once good and part of a complete friendship, becomes bad. He wonders whether one has an obligation to continue to commit to the friendship. He suggests that humans are responsible for trying to help their friends reconnect with good. It is only when the bad overcomes the good and the friend cannot be pulled away from the bad that the friendship should be dissolved.

Aristotle also explores the nature of self-love, or befriending oneself. Just as a complete friendship is centered on a desire to help the other achieve the most good, the relationship with the self should pursue the same. Aristotle calls the person who enters this kind of personal relationship an “excellent person” (167). This type of person enjoys spending time alone and finds satisfaction in memory. Later in the book, Aristotle questions whether one should love oneself and how this love diverges from selfishness. He denounces the notion that all self-love is a shameful act. The philosopher recognizes that certain types of self-love that are rooted in intemperance and incontinence are vices and devoid of justice. However, pure self-love that is focused on doing what is right is praiseworthy.

Aristotle then looks at the various features of friendship. Goodwill is a key component and is not the same thing as love. Instead, goodwill is the condition with which friendship begins. Even relationships of great passion, including erotic passion, must start with goodwill. It does not preface friendships that are based on utility or pleasure; goodwill undergirds only those that are founded upon love. Concord is another essential aspect of friendship and means more than merely having the same beliefs or similar views. In fact, those with dissimilar beliefs can still achieve harmony. Concord occurs when both parties act in ways that contribute to the desired effects of the friendship. Another feature of friendship is benevolence, as friendships are about mutual exchange.

The philosopher argues that friendships are vital to happiness. He disputes the argument that the person who achieves the highest level of good is no longer in need of friendships; this would be an unworthy punishment. Believing that a happy person is without a need for friendship implies that friendship is only about mutual benefit. In an earlier book, Aristotle suggests that happiness is about action: The happy person is engaged in constant activity of good. Friendships are essential to ensuring the continuity of this activity. When good people spend time together, goodness can thrive. Friendships of love, or complete friendships, are few. It would be unreasonable—and, perhaps, impossible—to pursue numerous friendships of love. They persist through various life experiences, good and bad. The excellent person who achieves happiness engages in rich and meaningful friendships with others. The excellent person also actively pursues a rich and meaningful friendship with the self. 

Book 10 Summary

The focus of Book 10 is pleasure. Although humans are closer to the divine, they are also still animals, and animals are primarily preoccupied with matters of pleasure. Therefore, parents use pleasure and pain to instruct small children, whom Aristotle suggests are closer to states of animalia. It is wrong to look at pleasure and pain as either good or bad. Rather, each state informs whether the action is good or bad, and each can also play a role in the excesses of vice. Because pleasure and pain are both feelings, they cannot be rationally blamed for vice. Feelings are not quantifiable by facts.

Some philosophers argue that pleasure is good. It is the thing that all animals seek, and its enjoyment can be attributed to its goodness. This thought coincides with the belief that pain is purely bad, to be avoided at all opportunities. Aristotle presents a different view of pleasure and pain. He suggests that these arguments do not represent the many nuances of the two states. Pleasure and pain operate on a scale. Just as virtue is the mean and vice is the outlying extreme, pleasure and pain have a moderate effect that is good and an extreme effect that is bad. Pleasure and pain cannot be entirely good or entirely bad because they are not complete states of being in this way. They are, however, complete entities on their own.

Therefore, pleasure is not good, but it is a good. Aristotle argues that pleasure is more activity than it is feeling, state of being, virtue, or vice. Pleasure does not persist in humans because humans grow tired. No activity can last forever. It must reveal itself in cycles. Aristotle compares the concept of activity to life. He argues that life and pleasure are intrinsically linked. Humans seek pleasure because they seek to live; humans seek life because they seek pleasure.

Finally, Aristotle revisits the topic of happiness, the goal of human ambition. Happiness is not a state of being. Instead, it is the “character of actions that are in accord with virtue” (192). Although some may think that happiness is about the pursuit of pleasure, it is independent of entertainment. Happiness is good, the outcome of correct living. Aristotle considers it as being closer to activity than as a state. True happiness is achieved through understanding and truth.

Happiness and understanding distinguish humans from the animal world and characterize human divinity. Aristotle suggests that humans should endeavor to be as close to the divine as possible, to attempt to reach beyond mortality. This is done through virtue. Aristotle looks once more at the various virtues that contribute to happiness. He suggests happiness becomes complete in many of the virtues: in understanding, in study, in generosity. Study rises above the rest because it concerns itself with all the virtues and is the most divine. Aristotle ends as he began. He presents a summary of what is known based upon his own study and pursuit of knowledge and asks that the reader engage in a discussion and continue the work.

Books 7-10 Analysis

Throughout the work, Aristotle presents several dichotomies: good and bad; pleasure and pain; continence and incontinence; virtue and vice. Each virtue is paired with corresponding vices. Aristotle argues in previous books that pleasure and pain contribute to the human understanding of good. They serve as a compass. They are fine in moderation, as they represent a mean. The theme of Finding Balance in Virtue explores Aristotle’s approach of equilibrium. Rather than advocating strongly for extremes, he proposes that humans find a way to incorporate evenness in their lives. Even friendships must be built upon a foundation of equality to be functional and mutually beneficial toward goodness.

Aristotle’s view of balance is revolutionary within his cultural context and even resembles Eastern philosophical tradition. The idea that aiming toward virtue may at times require dabbling in vice was novel in his era. The following analogy illustrates this concept: A person decides to go skydiving. While standing at the precipice, they weigh their options. They may go back into the plane, where they can land safely, or they may jump into the abyss. Virtue would mean facing fear and jumping out of the plane. The vices would be cowardice (retreating into the plane) and recklessness (jumping without a parachute). Regardless of the option the person chooses, going through that experience involves reconciling with vice and choosing from multiple options. The desire to retreat will be strong. By examining and confronting the extremes, the person can achieve virtue.

The types of friendships Aristotle discusses reflect the book’s broader concept concerning the placement of the individual in society. At all times, Aristotle recognizes that there is the good of man and the good of society, and these two are intrinsically linked. Community is extremely important because it allows individuals to work together and support one another. Complete friendships are predicated upon a desire to achieve happiness. Each person offers guidance, truthfulness, wit, and wisdom and encourages the other to live in accordance with virtue as well. This idea is reflected in the theme The Importance of Relationships for Good. Without community, individuals live in a state of inaction. In previous sections, Aristotle challenges the idea that inaction can lead to a virtuous life. Although the inactive individual may not impose harm upon others, this person does no good for others or for the self.

Community is necessary to achieve and pursue real virtue. People who live in a community of balance and equality can then achieve happiness, as found in the theme The Meanings of Good and Happiness. Happiness is about right action, the best way of living. Aristotle rejects the belief that one who achieves ultimate happiness has no need for friends. This is because friendship is also about joy and pleasure, not simply about what one takes from the relationship. It would be a punishment to limit someone who achieved the ultimate happiness to a life without friendship.

Readers may find Aristotle’s conclusion puzzling. In earlier books, he projects happiness as a type of transcendent experience, a state of achievement or complete good. In the final book, he argues that it is an activity aligned with virtues; Aristotle scholars now refer to this as “inclusivism.” He also presents the idea that happiness is really achieved only through study, understanding, and contemplation. This reflects Aristotle’s own experiences: He found joy and pleasure in his pursuit of knowledge and wisdom and recognizes them as endeavors that separate humans from the animal world and bring them closer to divine states of being. However, Aristotle acknowledges that others may find a path to happiness through other forms of virtue.

The key concept, he reminds the reader, is the importance of balance in all things. Pleasure and pain in extremes can lead to vice and bypass happiness. The extremities of vice always miss the mark of virtue. One must love others and love oneself. One must be just and temperate, continent and generous. Balance is about duality, an equilibrium of scales. Because all humans seek happiness, they must seek balance. In Aristotle’s view, this is the staircase to divine wholeness. Aristotle ends by reminding the reader of the ultimate aim: happiness. To achieve this happiness, the individual must engage with virtue, especially virtues of thought.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text