57 pages • 1 hour read
Martin HeideggerA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
Despite his efforts in Chapters 3 and 4, Heidegger’s account of Dasein is still incomplete. The introduction of temporality to his previous analysis of our being-in-the-world has cast both time and our relation to the world in a new light. To fully understand the connection between the two, and Dasein’s temporality, he must now look at a further element: He must take into account Dasein’s broader relation to time by looking both at our relation to the ordinary conception of time and at history.
Taking the latter first, Heidegger draws a distinction between history and what he calls “historiology as the science of history” (427). “Historiology” is the study or academic discipline we call “history”; “historicality” is our being as historical—our relationship to a broader human past transcending our individual past. Heidegger begins with historicality, as this is what grounds and is necessary to a proper understanding of historiology. What does it mean for something to be historical in this sense? To address this question, Heidegger starts by looking at why certain artefacts are considered historical, and he discusses potential answers to this question. He argues, ultimately, that it is because “that world within which they belonged to a context of equipment and were encountered as ready-to-hand and used by a concernful Dasein […] is no longer” (432). For example, a spinning jenny is historical not because of its age but because it is no longer part of a living context where it can be meaningfully engaged as ready-to-hand.
Heidegger goes on to discuss the distinction between authentic and inauthentic historicality. Like the way curiosity relates to the future, inauthentic historicality treats the past as something “present.” It uses present-at-hand information from the current moment to reimagine the past as a kind of pseudo-present. That is, it has an ontological status effectively no different from our own, but just not existing at the current moment. Indeed, such a view is what then underscores various problems in the philosophy of time and leads to theories such as eternalism. With this theory, past, present, and future are all held to exist, like spatial locations; it is just that we call “present” where our attention happens to be focused.
In contrast, authentic historicality “understands history as the ‘recurrence’ of the possible” (444). In this sense, an authentic relation to history consists in becoming aware of, and bringing to light, the possibilities latent in history. As such, history becomes not a distinct and dead dimension of the present-at-hand, but something that is living through and in us. This is why Heidegger talks about the idea of Dasein drawing from history a “hero” who can inspire a repetition of a life authentically lived. It is also why he alludes to the second of Nietzsche’s Untimely Mediations (1876), for Nietzsche employs a similar conception of history as inspiring or “monumental.” Further, Heidegger discusses the role of history in connection with a community or people, and he calls “Destiny” the authentic realization of a people of their common fate.
Heidegger goes on to explore our ordinary conception of time, specifically looking at its origins. He argues that our normal understanding of time originates not in any “objective” measurement of time, or codification of it, as we see expressed in clocks and watches. Rather, it is initially based in our involvement and coping in the world, and with other Dasein. Thus, our activity and projects create a lived, ready-to-hand time, organized around when certain things needed doing, such as the collection of the harvest. This only later leads to watch or clock time. This original readiness-to-hand of time, though, is misinterpreted as present-at-hand objective time by everyday Dasein. Such a misinterpretation of the origins of our conception of time also contributes to a certain philosophical interpretation of time. This is the idea of time as a succession of present-at-hand “nows” and of this succession being “infinite” (476).
Heidegger ends Being and Time by summing up what has been accomplished so far. He suggests that while progress has been made, through Dasein and temporality, the text is still only a “point of departure” for a broader and deeper analysis into Being (487). What precise form this will take is unclear, but it will involve a return to the problem and nature of Dasein’s time itself, now with a clearer sense of the direction this project should take. He also warns that such a project must remain vigilant to the ever-present threat of “reification,” a process whereby true understanding is dragged back towards the categories and ontology of presence.
As is clear from Chapters 5 and 6, Dasein does not just stand in a relation to its own temporality. It exists in relation to the temporality of a wider human community. Just as I must contend with my own past, in which I have lived a given way, and a future which I am in the process of becoming, so, too, with the group. My life is oriented towards constellations of others, and a society, and this society has a definitive and evolving past, and a future, in which certain human possibilities become either enhanced or restricted. Indeed, one is not possible without the other. Consider France in July of 1940. The possibilities for you of collaborating with the German occupation or of resisting it only make sense, and exist at all, because of the particular way history has unfolded at that moment. So, the converse is true. That there is a human history in which the Second World War came about in the first place is intelligible only because of the possibilities that countless Dasein chose to actualize.
All of this does not seem especially controversial. That Dasein’s existence as possibility is always situated in, and therefore must always take account of, the future of groups of others and what we call history, seems to follow naturally from what was said in previous chapters. Nor is it surprising that Heidegger should want to emphasize this point, kept until now in parentheses, in the context of a broader discussion of temporality. What is controversial is the relation authenticity plays to all this. Heidegger claims, regarding this, that “Dasein’s fateful destiny in and with its ‘generation’ goes to make up the full authentic historizing of Dasein” (436). In other words, it is not just that we must have a relation to peoples, to groups, and to history. Nor is just that authenticity can only take place within such a context, and by recognizing it. It is, rather, or additionally, that we must embrace and become part of the “destiny” of a group, “in communicating and struggling” alongside it (436). This is not one possible route to authenticity either; for Heidegger, it the ultimate path to authenticity, a necessary condition for any “fully” authentic life.
But why? Even if we adopted the weaker version of the claim, that authenticity is compatible with becoming part of the struggles and “destiny” of a group rather than requiring it, problems still abound. For one thing, who exactly are this group? Heidegger refers to “a community” and “a people” (436), but it is unclear to what these terms refer. If it is a national group, such as “the Germans” or “the Scottish,” then he seems to be venturing into the realms of nationalistic myth. We cannot, in any concretely meaningful or literal way, communicate with or struggle alongside such a vast and differentiated group of Dasein. On the other hand, if a “community” is an actual group of people with whom we have a possible relation, in the way one talks of a “local community,” it is hard to see what sense can be made of “destiny”. A concrete community may have, at times, a shared purpose, but this tends to be localized and limited. Its actual destiny, understood in any more significant sense, is a function of broader historical forces over which it has little or no influence.
That said, one might appeal to a certain argument about “culture” to defend Heidegger here. Something like what Nietzsche says in The Birth of Tragedy (1872) could be applied. Put very briefly, this would consist of two main elements. First, we might say that a truly authentic life can only emerge from a truly authentic culture. In fact, this coincides with a claim Heidegger makes about the they. This is that: “The extent to which its dominion becomes compelling and explicit may change in the course of history” (167). This suggests that our capacity for full authenticity is dependent on living in a culture that at least permits this as a possibility. The second element is more problematic. Since the goal is authenticity, to live the most authentic life possible would mean to struggle for a culture or society in which authenticity stands the best chance of flourishing. For Nietzsche in The Birth of Tragedy, this meant striving for a rebirth of German culture through the promotion of a new “tragic” artform. For Heidegger it could mean struggling for a society in which the organs of the they were controlled and tamed. For example, this might be achieved by collective efforts to limit the influence of newspapers, television, and mass culture.
However, there are also obvious issues with this. First, even assuming such a position could be attributed to Heidegger, the second claim does not seem to follow necessarily from the first. To be authentic does not automatically mean working for the potential authenticity of others, even if this is possible. This would be analogous to Sartre’s argument in Existentialism is a Humanism (1946), that to realize one’s being as free one must pursue the freedom of others. More significantly, the two claims might be said to be in conflict. This highlights a deeper worry with Heidegger’s discussion of history and authenticity. That is, to work towards a collective goal, in this case possible authenticity in a better society, seems still to involve a possibility that is not mine. The collective endeavor and striving required to enact any meaningful social change involve a sacrifice in authenticity—one that a reader invested in the values of Being and Time might be unwilling to make.