70 pages • 2 hours read
Robert NozickA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
In the Preface of Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Robert Nozick announces one of the book’s central themes: “the nature of the state, its legitimate functions and its justifications” in relation to individual rights (ix). His premise is that individuals have inalienable rights that limit what others, including the state, can do to them. In the Preface, Nozick also presents the main conclusions of his book:
[A] minimal state, limited to the narrow functions of protection against force, theft, fraud, enforcement of contracts, and so on, is justified; that any more extensive state will violate persons’ rights not to be forced to do certain things, and is unjustified; and that the minimal state is inspiring as well as right (ix).
Nozick addresses how he acquired his libertarian views, which favor a minimal state and oppose coercive state actions for wealth redistribution or personal protection. He acknowledges that others may find his ideas controversial and off-putting. He admits that he himself was initially reluctant to accept these views but was eventually persuaded by various arguments and considerations, which he presents in the book. Part 1 argues against the anarchist belief that a state is inherently violent and immoral. Nozick argues that a state can arise from anarchy and without rights violations. In doing so, he also addresses moral views, animal treatment, and fairness. In Part 2, he contends that no state beyond a minimal one is justifiable. He further critiques distributive justice theories and then presents the minimal state as an inspiring utopia.
Nozick makes it clear that his book is not just a political statement but a philosophical exploration of various issues, such as moral constraints on action, the treatment of animals, and theories of justice. Nozick situates his views in opposition to John Rawls’s theory of distributive justice, which relies on an extensive state to guarantee equality among its people. Instead, Nozick announces that he will develop his own entitlement theory that does not require more than a minimal state.
Nozick acknowledges the unfinished nature of his arguments in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, emphasizing the exploratory and provisional nature of his work. He invites readers to consider alternative viewpoints from the ones they may hold about the nature of individual rights, the state, and the concept of justice.
Political Philosophy
Nozick’s first chapter starts by questioning the necessity of a state. He considers the anarchist alternative of a non-state situation and suggests exploring a “state of nature”—the hypothetical idea of how people lived before creating societies—to understand the implications of a world without a government. This examination, he argues, is crucial for determining whether a state is morally justifiable or if an anarchic situation, in which people generally act morally, could be better. The chapter emphasizes the role of moral philosophy—rights and wrongs as determined by a culture—in setting the boundaries for political philosophy and the legitimacy of state power.
Explanatory Political Theory
Nozick identifies three possible perspectives when viewing politics: as related to the non-political, as originating from the non-political but not reducible to it, and as an autonomous realm. He argues that the first approach offers the most comprehensive understanding. Thus, he proposes to start with a non-political situation and show how a political situation would emerge from it.
Nozick relates the non-political situation to state-of-nature theories. Nozick argues that state-of-nature theories provide insight into human morality outside of the state, even if these theories are not factually accurate. Nozick identifies three types of potential explanations: fact-defective explanations, which rely on false starting conditions; law-defective explanations, which rely on false law-like statements; and fundamental potential explanations, which are not necessarily correct but remain informative for understanding a realm. Nozick argues that state-of-nature theories are fundamental potential explanations and have great explanatory potential.
Thus, state-of-nature theories help examine how states arise and why they might differ from theoretical models. This approach follows the tradition of John Locke, although Nozick claims that Locke’s explanation of the law of nature in his Second Treatise is insufficient.
In the beginning of Chapter 2, Nozick discusses John Locke’s state of nature, in which individuals have total freedom of action and decision if they abide by the law of nature. The law of nature prohibits harming others in their “life, health, liberty, or possessions” (10).
However, individuals do sometimes transgress the law of nature, which leads to self-defense and punishment. Nozick underlines the limitations of this state, such as inadequate natural law for all situations, biased personal judgment, disproportionate retribution, and endless feuds.
Protective Associations
In this section, Nozick imagines how issues within a state of nature can be addressed. As an example, he uses the formation of groups of individuals who enforce their rights and protect themselves. Such groups lead to the formation of mutual-protection associations, and these formations face challenges, for example, in their availability for defense. There is also the risk of members of the protective associations abusing their power. Nozick notes that protective services can become specialized and commercialized, offering protection as a service for a fee.
Some individuals may seek arbitration outside the system of protection associations, which can lead back to state-run legal systems. However, Nozick claims that a state-run legal system limits individuals’ options for the private enforcement of justice, leaving those who do not wish to submit to the state’s system without options.
Nozick focuses on the possible conflicts between clients of different protective agencies in a state of nature. He proposes three scenarios: one agency consistently wins battles, leading to a monopoly; agencies dominate different geographical areas, resulting in territorial divisions; or equally successful agencies decide to avoid costly conflicts and rely on a third party for arbitration, leading to a judicial system.
All these scenarios, argues Nozick, lead to a situation resembling a minimal state. Nozick questions why a market for protection services tends toward monopoly, attributing it to the unique nature of the service in which the strength of competition directly affects the value of protection.
Invisible-Hand Explanations
In this section of Chapter 2, Nozick compares a dominant protective association with the state. He questions Locke’s idea of the emergence of money from an agreement. He argues that in a barter system, individuals gravitate toward more marketable goods without a formal agreement, a process explained by “invisible-hand explanations” (18). This term, which Nozick borrows from Adam Smith, describes complex patterns that unintentionally arise from individual actions. This contrasts with “hidden-hand explanations” (19), which bring together disparate facts and claim they are patterns of someone’s intentional design. Nozick likens hidden-hand explanations to conspiracy theories.
Further, Nozick explores different types of invisible-hand processes, focusing on the establishment of patterns within filtering and equilibrium processes. Filtering permits only compatible elements, removing the rest, while in equilibrium, each component adapts to its surroundings, and these collective adaptations together shape the overall pattern.
Lastly, Nozick notes that methodological individualism might overlook social filtering processes that explain why all instances of a phenomenon fit a certain pattern. Methodological individualism is the principle that explanations in political and social science should focus on information regarding individuals and their relationships, avoiding the consideration of broader social structures.
Is the Dominant Protective Association a State?
Nozick identifies two differences between private protective associations and the minimal state: private enforcement of rights and selective protection. He notes that Max Weber and other political thinkers consider the monopoly on force within a geographical area to be an essential condition for the constitution of a state. However, Nozick argues that the monopoly on force is neither a sufficient nor necessary condition for statehood. He thinks that a state announces its intention to punish unauthorized use of force, unlike private agencies, which are not required to do so. In addition, private agencies offer protection to those who buy their service, unlike a state, which protects all individuals within its jurisdiction. Nozick concludes that despite initial appearances, the dominant protective agency in a territory does not fulfill these criteria, thus not constituting a state.
The Minimal State and the Ultraminimal State
In the first section of Chapter 3, Nozick introduces the concept of the ultraminimal state, distinguishing it from the night-watchman state. The ultraminimal state maintains a monopoly on force but only offers protection and enforcement services to those who purchase its policies. The night-watchman state, which Nozick also calls the minimal state, protects all citizens through a redistributive plan financed through taxation.
Nozick poses several questions regarding the legitimacy of redistributive functions for protective services and whether protection is a unique case for such redistribution. He also asks whether compelling non-redistributive reasons justify providing protective services for some at the expense of others.
Moral Constraints and Moral Goals
Further on, Nozick critiques utilitarian approaches to social organization and individual rights. He argues that utilitarianism, the ethical theory that promotes the greatest happiness for the largest number of individuals, could lead to compromising rights in favor of perceived greater happiness. Nozick contrasts this with a view in which rights place moral constraints on actions and not just end goals. This view prohibits violating these constraints for any purpose, unlike a goal-oriented position, whereby rights can be breached to minimize overall societal rights violations. Nozick also argues that the ultraminimal state should include constraints on certain actions to protect individuals’ rights.
Why Side Constraints?
In the third part of Chapter 3, Nozick discusses Kant’s categorical imperative, which states that individuals are ends in themselves and not merely means to be used. He argues that side constraints reflect the inviolability of individuals and protect against specific ways of using people. This contrasts with end-state views, which focus on minimizing the use of people as means altogether.
Nozick emphasizes the moral significance of recognizing individuals as separate entities with their own lives, arguing against using individuals for the benefit of a perceived social good.
Libertarian Constraints
Further on, Nozick discusses the moral justification for libertarian constraints. He argues that individuals have separate and distinct existences, which prohibits sacrificing one person for another. This idea leads to a libertarian constraint on initiating aggression because it requires respect for the separateness of individual life. Nozick notes that further steps are needed to fully develop this principle, especially in cases involving innocent threats or shields, where moral complexities arise concerning self-defense and aggression.
Constraints and Animals
In this section, Nozick examines moral side constraints as related to animal rights. He asks whether animals have moral status beyond mere objects for humans and if certain purposes justify imposing significant costs on them. Nozick argues that animals’ treatment should be weighed in moral deliberations.
Nozick asks whether animals should be sacrificed for greater overall happiness. He challenges the utilitarian thesis of the greater good because, he argues, even animals have claims to fair treatment despite being brought into existence for human use.
The Experience Machine
In the sixth section of Chapter 3, Nozick introduces the thought experiment of an “experience machine” that offers any experience to individuals. This machine requires individuals to be floating in a tank with electrodes connected to their brains. Thus, they would be able to experience anything they desire. This experiment presents the question of whether experiences matter only if they feel real “from the inside” and if one should choose to live a simulated life (42).
Nozick argues that people seek more than detached experiences; they want to do things in the world, have agency over the type of person they are, and have contact with reality at a more profound level. The experience machine experiment reveals that living an authentic life and engaging with reality directly is crucial to individuals because without experiencing the world, the machine is doing the living instead of the individuals floating in it. Therefore, mere thought experiences—even if pleasurable—are insufficient for a fulfilling life. This discussion leads to broader questions about what truly matters to humans beyond just sensory or thought experiences.
Underdetermination of Moral Theory
In this section, Nozick asks what distinguishes humans from animals and whether the difference justifies animals being treated as a means to an end (or against Kant’s moral imperative). He proposes a hierarchical moral scale with three statuses: beings that cannot be sacrificed (status 1), beings that can be sacrificed only for higher beings (status 2), and those that can be sacrificed for beings at the same or higher levels (status 3).
Nozick considers whether humans could belong to status 2. Furthermore, he uses an analogy involving hypothetical beings superior to humans who might sacrifice humans for their benefit.
What Are Constraints Based Upon?
Nozick questions whether moral views should be based on a side-constraint view or a more complex hierarchical structure. He asks what specific qualities necessitate moral constraints on how a person is treated by others. He considers traditional attributes, such as sentience, rationality, free will, and moral agency. However, he finds these insufficient for establishing a clear connection to moral constraints. Nozick raises ethical questions about moral judgments and the nature of human interactions with animals, suggesting that although animals are not rational beings capable of ethical decisions, it is nevertheless problematic to apply the utilitarian principle to their treatment.
Furthermore, Nozick suggests that the ability to formulate and live by an overall conception of one’s life is crucial. He asks whether interfering with someone’s life path undermines its meaningfulness. Nozick does not provide clear answers to this series of questions, stating that he plans to explore these moral and ethical issues further in future works.
The Individual Anarchist
In the final section of Chapter 3, Nozick revisits the concept of moral side constraints concerning the state and the private protection system. He discusses the individualist anarchist’s view that the state, by monopolizing force and compelling individuals to fund others’ protection, violates moral side constraints because it separates those who do not participate in the justice system (for example, peaceful individuals) from their right to not contribute to the protection of others.
Nozick argues that for a state to be morally legitimate, it must transition from a private protection scheme to an ultraminimal state—and then to a minimal state—without violating individual rights. He plans to justify this transition in the rest of the work, showing that a minimal state is the only morally permissible form of government because it balances individual rights and state responsibilities.
The first section of Anarchy, State, and Utopia addresses the moral legitimacy of the state in relation to individual rights. Nozick’s hypothesis revolves around the assertion that a minimal state is the most justifiable form of government, as it is the only one that provides a system of justice while respecting the inviolability of individual rights. This contention is a response to, and a critique of, prevailing theories of state and justice, particularly John Rawls’s theory of distributive justice and the utilitarian framework. Rawls’s theory in A Theory of Justice (1971) advances two key ideas: the liberty principle, which prioritizes basic liberties for individuals, such as the freedom of speech, assembly, and property, and the difference principle, which permits social and economic inequalities only if they ultimately benefit the least privileged in society. Rawls also advocates a theory of equal distribution of justice and goods in society.
Contrasting with Rawls’s acceptance of a more substantial role for the state in redistributing resources, Nozick argues for a minimal state limited to protecting individual rights against force and fraud. He proposes that any larger state would violate individuals’ rights by enforcing redistributive policies, which he opposes. In his discussion of the protective associations in Chapter 1, he posits that even in the beginning forms of governmental structure that the associations represent, one can notice the inherent tendency toward monopolization. The progression from an unorganized state of nature to a minimal state challenges traditional notions about the necessity and formation of government, offering an alternative perspective on the natural emergence of state-like entities. While Nozick does not impose a libertarian point of view, he does point to the issues that a more extensive state would pose for individual rights, which he considers paramount.
Nozick’s analysis of the state and individual rights is informed by modern moral philosophy. One of the main concepts he works with in Anarchy, State, and Utopia is the concept of moral side constraints, which claims that individual rights should not be treated as mere end goals but as constraints that inherently limit the actions one can morally justify. This approach is a departure from the classical theory of utilitarianism, which evaluates actions based on their outcomes for the greatest number. Nozick’s framework asserts the sacred nature of individual rights, emphasizing that these rights should not be infringed upon for the sake of a perceived greater good.
The discussion on animals in the book extends Nozick’s exploration of moral side constraints and questions the extent to which these constraints apply beyond human interactions. By positing that animals have a certain moral status, Nozick challenges the utilitarian view that animals can be used or sacrificed for human benefit. This not only diversifies the application of his moral theory but also raises questions about the nature and scope of moral consideration in a society. Nozick extends the analysis of animal rights in Chapter 3 to a potential interaction with extraterrestrial beings that relate to humans in the same way we relate to animals. Using this analogy, he demonstrates that relying on moral or rational developmental stages to justify treating animals as means rather than ends is problematic. While many arguments in favor of animal rights come from left-wing perspectives, Nozick illustrates how one might reach similar conclusions about animal exploitation from a libertarian lens.
Nozick’s example of the experience machine is instrumental in understanding his view of human life and experiences. He argues that authenticity and direct physical engagement with reality are essential for a fulfilling life, challenging the notion that remote experiences are enough. Although Nozick does not advance a theory of the soul or authenticity in Anarchy, State, and Utopia, the discussion of the thinking tank experiment suggests his preoccupation with such notions. Overall, in the first part of the book, Nozick establishes that the life of an individual is valuable in itself and that it is worthwhile to explore how the individual is acknowledged and recognized as inherently valuable.
In engaging with anarchist theory regarding the existence of the state and its infringement of individual rights, Nozick confronts the moral impasses posed by state formation and operation. The transition from a state of nature to a minimal state and the state’s monopoly on force are scrutinized for their moral legitimacy. Nozick argues that while the state’s role in protecting individual rights is necessary—highlighting The Difference Between Anarchism and Libertarianism as anarchism advocates for a completely stateless society—its authority should be confined to the minimal functions required to protect these rights. This stance on the minimal state is a counterpoint to more expansive views of state responsibilities and powers.