56 pages • 1 hour read
David HumeA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Hume now describes the “direct passions” (447), which he defines as emerging straight from pain and pleasure or good and evil. These include grief/joy, fear/hope, and desire/aversion. This is also how Hume sees the will, which he views as one of the “immediate effects” (447) of pain and pleasure.
Hume considers the question of whether human behavior emerges out of necessity (reactions based on the impressions and ideas formed through sensations) or liberty (total free will). Hume notes one argument that necessity does not drive human behavior: “Necessity is regular and certain. Human conduct is irregular and uncertain” (451). To this, Hume responds that the process through which we develop our experiences and ideas in response to the physical environment around us is similar to how we respond to human behavior, which Hume calls “moral evidence” (452). The causes driving the behavior of individual humans do vary, but humans actually do consistently act based on our own individual experiences, interests, and needs.
From there, Hume challenges the philosophical idea of liberty. He lays out a series of three objections. First, Hume argues that there is a distinction between liberty of indifference (our freedom not being bound by necessity) and liberty of spontaneity (our freedom to act as we choose). Hume criticizes philosophers for not often making a distinction between the two (455). Second, Hume asserts that we have a “false sensation or experience” (455) of liberty. For example, we believe in hindsight that we could have chosen differently and not acted out of necessity. Third, we believe necessity contradicts the idea that people have moral responsibility and can be used as an excuse to violate religious morals and the law. Hume counters that there are no social dangers in acknowledging that impressions and relations influence human behavior (456-57). Instead, Hume argues that necessity supports the idea of an individual’s moral responsibility. After all, Hume’s concept of necessity shows that people’s behavior does not come from just chance, but instead reveals that each individual has a moral character that forms the basis of their actions (458).
Next, Hume turns to the circumstances that do shape our free will. Hume begins by arguing against the influential notion that reason and emotion are always at odds. Instead, Hume argues that we use reason as a tool to make our actions or determine our goals, all of which are shaped by our passions (461). A passion can be rational and pure reason itself is not always rational. As Hume puts it, “Tis not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger” (463). Hume admits that a passion can come from a cause that is false or a relation that is not reasonable. However, in that case, it is not the passion itself that is false, but the judgment connected to the passion (463). Hume goes so far as to say the conflict between reason and the passions is really the conflict between violent passions and calm passions (464-65).
With that, Hume discusses the violent passions and why they influence us. He lists a number of circumstances in which one predominant passion can be made more violent by other passions. For example, a man’s love for his mistress might become more extreme if he also feels a little anger or hate toward her, and a soldier’s bravery might be stronger if he feels some fear (467). Custom may also increase or deaden the power of violent passions. At first, the repetition of an experience might strengthen a passion, but also eventually make even a pleasurable activity painful (470-71). Also, the passions can become more violent through the “vivacity” (471) or strength of our ideas. One such idea that increases vivacity is space and time, since, for example, the further away in distance in time and space something is, the less intense our emotion. Similarly, we hold more respect for an object or person from a great distance, like an ancient Greek medal (480). Hume theorizes this is because we place our respect for a great distance in space or time into an object. Hume argues that we have more respect for objects associated with the past than the future because we cannot go against the flow of time toward the past while we are naturally headed to the future.
Hume concludes by looking at the direct passions. He identifies two types: the direct passions, which come from pleasure and pain or good and evil, and those that arise from instinct (485-86). The first kind includes joy and grief, hope and fear, and desire and aversion. The will asserts itself when someone seeks pleasure or to be freed from pain. The second kind of direct passions include hunger, lust, anger, and benevolence. These do not arise from pleasure and pain, but they can cause pain and pleasure. Hume focuses on fear and hope. Passions of joy and grief are generated when the imagination examines different possibilities and “the chances are equal on both sides” (490). Depending on the object of the passions, the combination of grief and joy will produce either hope or fear.
The last passion Hume examines at length is curiosity, which Hume describes as “love of truth” (495). Curiosity is driven by our pleasure in seeking truths in either abstract subjects like mathematics, or in tangible areas like politics and natural philosophy. Such curiosity is made more vivid by our desire for an intellectual challenge and by our sympathy for those our research or scientific discoveries might help. Hume also argues that our curiosity is propelled by the pleasure we gain from the work itself, much like how a gambler might enjoy the distraction of the game more than even the challenge or the awards from winning (498-99).
Hume here fully develops an argument that he has been setting up throughout Book 2 of A Treatise of Human Nature: that there is no real conflict between the Passions and Reason. Hume’s argument is a response to another widely-shared assumption in Western philosophy, a view most strongly expressed by the ancient Roman Stoics: They maintained that the emotions have to be overcome through rational thought, or else they will lead to harmful actions or inaction.
Hume instead argues that “[a]bstract or demonstrative reasoning […] never influences any of our actions, but only as it directs our judgment concerning causes and effects” (461). In other words, we might grieve deeply for a beloved pet. To an outside observer, the grief might look so powerful that it seems irrational. However, from a purely rational perspective, our grief is understandable because we have lost a constant source of comfort that helped us deal with a lot of stress. On the other hand, reason might lead us to try to become an engineer, even though we have no interest in engineering, because the pay would be good. Hume would say that when we make decisions like choosing a career, we usually do and should listen to both reason and our passions. After all, it is not our passions that are wrong, but the judgments that bring about our passions (463), like falling in love with someone who does not actually care about us.
Besides emotions versus reason, Hume also takes aim at absolute free will in preparation for his arguments about morality in Book 3. In his own writing, Hume shows he is aware that his critics might accuse him of arguing that there is no free will and everyone is so shaped by their experience that they have no moral culpability in their actions. Hume counters that his view of human nature actually gives more weight to people’s moral choices (458-59). For example, we might have a fear of flying based on actual experience like a previous turbulent flight, a fear which has been reinforced through observation by seeing airplane crashes on movies and TV shows. However, we want to finally go to Brazil, a lifelong dream. We make the decision to take a flight to Brazil, despite our fear. Hume would suggest this proves that people are still capable of free choice despite the power of sensation and experience. Not only that, but our decision has more significance than it would if we had total liberty over our decisions, unhindered by our past experience.
Hume’s views here are similar to the foundations of modern psychology. We might accept that a criminal’s actions were shaped by a childhood trauma or by their bad circumstances in adulthood. However, this does not mean the criminal should not face any kind of punishment for their actions.
By David Hume