logo

80 pages 2 hours read

John Rawls

A Theory of Justice

Nonfiction | Reference/Text Book | Adult | Published in 1971

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Chapter 2Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Part 1

Chapter 2, Section 10 Section Summary: “Institutions and Formal Justice”

The principles of justice for institutions differ from the principles of justice for individuals. An institution is “a public system of rules which defines offices and positions with their rights and duties, powers, and immunities, and the like” (47). An institution’s rules—and each person’s participation in them—are the result of an agreement based on a public understanding of what is just and unjust. Therefore, an institution is measured as just or unjust by how it is effectively and impartially administered. In this way, formal justice is adherence to a system, the strength of which depends on the justice of the system’s institutions.

Chapter 2, Section 11 Section Summary: “Two Principles of Justice”

The two principles of justice are the equal liberty principle and the difference principle. These apply to both individuals and the institutions that govern society.

All basic liberties are equal under the first principle of justice. They include political liberty, freedom of speech and assembly, liberty of conscience and freedom of thought, freedom of the person, the right to hold personal property, and freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure. The second principle governs the distribution of income and wealth, and the design of institutions that assign different authorities and responsibilities in society.

The priority principle dictates that the first principle is given greater priority than the second principle, the result being that “infringements of the basic equal liberties protected by the first principle cannot be justified, or compensated for, by greater social and economic advantages” distributed by the second principle (53).

Basic liberties guaranteed by the first principle can be limited and compromised only when they conflict with other basic liberties. Distribution of income and wealth by the second principle must comply with the basic liberties and equality of opportunity. Further, all social values should be distributed equally, unless an unequal distribution is to everyone’s advantage. For example, if there are five people in a society, and one of these people is the leader, and all five people agree the leader should get more wealth due to leading, then an inequality of distribution would be warranted.

Chapter 2, Section 12 Section Summary: “The Second Principle”

Three interpretations of the two principles exist, in addition to a fourth interpretation of “natural aristocracy” that Rawls does not discuss. The three interpretations are the system of natural liberty, liberal equality, and democratic equality. These are complemented by the principle of efficiency, which states that a society produces all commodities equally, without prioritizing some over others.

Rawls states that the system of natural liberty ensures the principle of efficiency. However, the principle of efficiency can be applied to the basic structure of justice as fairness by stating that the basic structure is efficient when it cannot be altered to increase the prospects of some without correspondingly decreasing the prospects of others. There are many possible efficient arrangements of the basic structure, but not all are just. The system of natural liberty constrains the principle of efficiency through institutional requirements, resulting in an efficient distribution accepted as just.

Chapter 2, Section 13 Section Summary: “Democratic Equality and the Difference Principle”

The system of democratic equality combines the principle of fair equality of opportunity with the difference principle. In this system, prospects must not be secured for those better off unless doing so would advantage the less fortunate.

The difference principle dictates that an unequal distribution should only be tolerated if it increases the prospects of all parties. Otherwise, an equal distribution is preferred. If an equal distribution cannot be achieved, an unequal distribution is justifiable only if the inequality is to the advantage of the worse off.

In this respect, the difference principle accords with the principle of efficiency because the difference principle is satisfied when it is impossible to increase the prospects of any one representative person without decreasing those of another. Inequalities are chain-connected: If an inequality raises a representative person in the lowest position, it raises those in all positions in between, and therefore “everyone benefits when the difference principle is satisfied” (70).

Further, a close-knit group ensures that the difference principle operates in the correct order because the principle will first maximize the welfare of the worst-off representative person, followed by the second worst-off, then the third, and so on, until reaching the best-off representative person.

Chapter 2, Section 14 Section Summary: “Fair Equality of Opportunity and Pure Procedural Justice”

The second part of the second principle of justice as fairness is the liberal principle of fair equality of opportunity. The principle of open positions forbids excluding groups from positions because those excluded would feel unjustly treated, even if they receive a greater benefit from the efforts of those allowed to obtain such positions. Rawls states that such excluded groups “would be deprived of one of the main forms of human good” (73), and adds that “[t]he role of the principle of fair opportunity is to insure that the system of cooperation is one of pure procedural justice” (76).

Justice as fairness produces a society motivated by cooperative venture for mutual advantage. This system treats distributive shares as a matter of pure procedural justice: A scheme of justice that dictates a fair procedure that, if followed, will result in a fair outcome, whatever it is, through the construction and impartial administration of a just system of institutions. Utilitarianism, by contrast, follows imperfect procedural justice, which has an independent criterion for the correct outcome but no procedure guaranteed to arrive at the outcome.    

The notions of the basic structure, the veil of ignorance, of a lexical order, of the least-favored position, and of procedural justice, taken independently, do not produce a system of justice, but combined, they provide a basic structure for the concept of justice as fairness.

Chapter 2, Section 15 Section Summary: “Primary Social Goods as the Basis of Expectations”

When comparing goods within the framework of social justice, objective grounds to which persons can recognize and agree should be established. The difference principle establishes objective grounds for interpersonal comparisons in two ways. First, once the least-advantaged representative person is identified, only ordinal judgments of well-being are applied. Second, the difference principle simplifies the basis of interpersonal comparisons.

The primary social goods are rights, liberties and opportunities, and income and wealth: “[A] person’s good is determined by what is for him the most rational long-term plan of life given reasonably favorable circumstances,” with a rational plan being one that cannot be improved (79).

In contrast to the basic liberties, primary social goods are not always equal, as justice as fairness “assume[s] that the members of society are rational persons able to adjust their conceptions of the good to their situation” (81). The systems established by justice as fairness allow persons to pursue the social goods they desire without making value judgments on specific social goods.

Chapter 2, Section 16 Section Summary: “Relevant Social Positions”

In justice as fairness, a person holds two social positions: a position of equal citizenship and a position defined by the person’s place in the distribution of income and wealth. The basic structure should be appraised from the position of equal citizenship, which is defined by the rights and liberties of the principle of equal liberty and the principle of fair equality of opportunity.

The second position, a person’s place in the distribution of income and wealth, is more difficult to precisely define. It is argued that the least-advantaged group is defined by those least favored in family and class origins, natural endowments, and luck in the course of life, but Rawls concedes that some arbitrariness exists in defining this group. Once the relevant positions are established, judgments made from their perspective override claims from more particular situations; that is, the general point of view is preferred to the specific, detailed perspective: “By selecting the so-called starting places one follows out the idea of mitigating the effects of natural accident and social circumstance” (85).

Chapter 2, Section 17 Summary: “The Tendency to Equality”

The two principles express an egalitarian conception of justice. The difference principle incorporates the principle of redress by compensating for the inequalities of birth and natural endowment. Incorporating the principle of redress removes any emphasis on social efficiency and technocratic values from the basic structure. The difference principle is also a principle of mutual benefit because it incorporates reciprocity.

The difference principle incorporates the principle of fraternity by eliminating the desire for greater advantage unless it’s to the benefit of those less well-off. The democratic interpretation of the two principles of justice incorporates the traditional ideas of liberty, equality, and fraternity as follows: “[L]iberty corresponds to the first principle, equality to the idea of equality in the first principle together with equality of fair opportunity, and fraternity to the difference principle” (91).

Chapter 2, Section 18 Summary: “Principles for Individuals: The Principle of Fairness”

The order of adoption for a society should be as follows: principles for the basic structure of society, principles for individuals, principles for the law of nations, and priority rules (which may be tentatively adopted earlier and revised later).

The principle of fairness accounts for all requirements and obligations that are not natural duties and holds that a person must abide by the rules of an institution if the institution is just (satisfies the two principles of justice) and the person has voluntarily accepted the benefits of the institution.

The principle of fairness is an obligation arising from a contractual agreement. Obligations are distinct from other moral requirements and have three characteristics: they arise from voluntary acts, the content of the obligation is specified by the rules of an institution, and obligations are owed to definite persons cooperating to maintain the arrangement from which the obligation arose. For this reason, the contractual nature of the principle of fairness dictates that a person cannot be bound to unjust institutions.

Chapter 2, Section 19 Summary: “Principles for Individuals: The Natural Duties”

A natural duty can be positive (the duty of mutual aid) in that it requires action, or negative (the duty not to harm) because it requires refraining from action. Rawls states that “[n]egative duties have more weight than positive ones” (98). Natural duties apply regardless of a person’s voluntary acts and have no connection to institutions or social practices. Though derived from contract theory, the principles of natural duty do not require consent or any voluntary act: “From the standpoint of justice as fairness, a fundamental natural duty is the duty of justice. This duty requires us to support and to comply with just institutions that exist and apply to us” (99).

Chapter 2 Analysis

Chapter 2 details the two main principles of justice in Rawls’s theory. This highlights the theme of Balancing Individual Rights with the Common Good. The first principle of justice guarantees equal basic liberties to all persons and the second principle dictates that social goods be distributed in a way that is to every person’s advantage and attached to opportunities open to all. The guarantee of an equal right to basic liberties is given priority in the two principles of justice. This means that a person’s liberty cannot be reduced to obtain a larger distributive share of social goods under the second principle.

This prioritizing of the first principle over the second produces one of the main tensions present in Rawls’s theory of how justice as fairness could function in the real world, as it directly opposes utilitarianism, which is the theory on which most of Western society is based. In a capitalist utilitarian society, the common good is usually defined by wealth, which means that the wealthiest individuals and institutions are perceived as providing the most benefit to the common good even if they infringe upon individual rights. Rawls counters this notion with the difference principle, which states that social goods should be distributed equally among persons and that if any inequalities must exist, they should exist to benefit all persons, especially those worst off. In this scenario, the most advantaged can only increase their distributive share if no one else’s share is reduced, and the least advantaged increase their share. This is where The Importance of Institutions in Maintaining Fairness comes into play.

Institutions guard against basing distribution on talent, which can disadvantage the least well-off members of society. The system of natural liberty, as implemented by institutions, permits injustice by distributing based on morally arbitrary qualities such as social circumstance, chance contingencies, and good or bad fortune. The system of liberal equality attempts to correct this inequality by incorporating the principle of fair equality of opportunity.

Rawls admits that this system is not without flaws. The system of liberal equality dictates that persons with the same ability and the same willingness to use their ability should face the same prospects regardless of their initial place in the social system. However, it is impossible in practice to guarantee equal prospects to those with similar abilities and will, and therefore the system of liberal equality is also defective. The antidote is the system of democratic equality, which when used in conjunction with the difference principle treats all persons equally and does not distribute based on morally arbitrary qualities. It is therefore the best choice among the four possible systems.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text